INFORMATION, INDIVIDUAL ERRORS, AND COLLECTIVE PERFORMANCE:

EMPIRICAL EVIDENCE ON THE CONDORCET JURY THEOREM
 
 

Nicholas R. Miller
Department of Political Science
University of Maryland Baltimore County
Baltimore, Maryland 21228

May, 1994

Running Head: Individual Errors and Collective Performance
Key Words: information, individual errors, collective performance, majority rule, Condorcet Jury Theorem
Submitted to Group Decision and Negotiation
 
 
 
 
 

INFORMATION, INDIVIDUAL ERRORS, AND COLLECTIVE PERFORMANCE:
EMPIRICAL EVIDENCE ON THE CONDORCET JURY THEOREM

Abstract

The Condorcet Jury Theorem implies that the collective performance of group, in arriving at a "correct" judgment on the basis of majority or plurality rule, will be superior to the average performance of individual members of the group, if certain apparently plausible conditions hold. Variants of the Jury Theorem are reviewed, particularly including the more politically-relevant variant that allows for conflicting interests within the group. We then examine two kinds of empirical data. First, we compare individual and collective performance in a large number of multiple-choice tests, and we find that collective performance invariably and substantially exceeds average individual performance. Second, we analyze American National Election Study data to create dichotomous-choice tests concerning positions of candidates on a variety of political issues, and Condorcet-like effects are again evident. Finally, continuing to use NES data, we construct, on each political issue, a simulated referendum (direct voting on the issue) and election (indirect voting on the issue by voting for candidates on the basis of their perceived positions on the issue), and we compare the two results. "Electoral error" is quite small, providing evidence of Condorcet-like effects in a situation of conflicting preferences.
 

1. Information and the Political Process

        One of the most persistent descriptive themes in voting studies over the last four decades or so has been that individual voters are poorly informed and generally fail abysmally to meet, or even to approach, the requirements of citizenship postulated by the "classical doctrine" of democracy (in the sense of Schumpeter, 1942). At the same time, sophisticated observers of politics might be hard put to name a single recent national election in which the vote division plausibly would have been substantially different, even if all voters had in fact made more complete use of the information potentially available to them. To quote V. O. Key, Jr. (1966, p. 7):

To be sure, many individual voters act in odd ways indeed; yet in the large the electorate behaves about as rationally and responsibly as we should expect, given the clarity of the alternatives presented to it and the character of the information available to it.
        This discrepancy between inferior performance by individual voters and apparently superior performance by the electorate collectively has been asserted by others as well (e.g., Berelson, Lazarsfeld, and McPhee et al., 1954, p. 312; Page and Shapiro, 1992.) However, if the contrast between individual and collective political performance has fairly frequently been noted, the precise mechanisms that produce it were at one time less well understood.

        In recent decades, however, social scientists have developed a clearer understanding of both why individual voters are typically poorly informed and why electorates may nevertheless collectively perform rather well.

        While voter ignorance is often condemned or, in any case, attributed to individual irrationality, typically low levels of voter information can actually be attributed to voter rationality, not irrationality, according to the argument originally set out by Anthony Downs (1957).

        First, information is in some measure costly to obtain (beyond some minimal amount that may be freely available in any individual's environment) and to process. In addition, information is typically subject to diminishing marginal returns (and perhaps increasing marginal costs as well). It therefore almost never pays even an individual decision maker to become fully informed, because marginal information costs exceed marginal information returns at some point well short of complete information.

        So even individual decision makers rationally choose to remain considerably uninformed. But for a participant in a collective decision making process, such as a voter, the incentive to acquire information is far more attenuated. Making the correct decision now becomes a public good, while information is still purchased individually, so information gathering presents a collective action problem of the familiar sort and one that it is more severe the larger the group. For whatever the individual's incentive to acquire information before, it must now be discounted by the probability that his vote will be pivotal, and this probability becomes exceeding small as group size increases. Thus everyone in the decision making group rationally chooses to remain largely uninformed. This phenomenon, which has been dubbed rational ignorance, must be taken as a fundamental characteristic of mass elections and of mass politics generally.

        There are, however, at least two positive twists to the story of rational ignorance.

        1. A little information can go a long way -- quite poorly informed individuals often make correct choices. This is most evident in the kind of dichotomous choice presented in typical two-candidate or two-party elections or in yes/no referenda. An individual who has acquired just a few bits of information is very far from completely informed and could improve his probability of choosing correctly by acquiring addition information, but he is already quite likely to choose correctly. (This observation is just the converse of the observation that information is subject to diminishing marginal returns -- the first few bit are worth a great deal.) Theoretical and experimental research by McKelvey and Ordeshook (1985, 1986, 1990) particularly supports this argument.

        The second positive twist is the focus of the analysis in the present essay.

        2. A group choice (based on majority or plurality rule) can be correct, even if many individuals in the group make errors. Thus, while individual members of a collective decision-making group have very little incentive to acquire information, if members do acquire some information and cast their votes independently, then -- even though many individuals will vote "incorrectly" -- it is very likely that the voting outcome will be "correct." This is a consequence of the Jury Theorem of Condorcet (see Black, 1958, pp. 159-180; Grofman, 1975, 1978; Grofman, Owen, Shapley, and Feld, 1981; Grofman and Feld, 1988) to which we now turn.
 

2. Condorcet Jury Theorem Variants

        There are a number of variants of the Condorcet Jury Theorem, which we informally review here.

        1. The "All Gray" Model. In its simplest form, the Condorcet Jury Theorem says this: suppose that each individual in a decision making group has a given level of "competence," i.e., a given probability p of making a correct choice in a dichotomous choice situation. We may think of this level of competence as determined by his level of information, and it is here taken to be the same for all members (hence "all gray"). Then, assuming only that these members are at least minimally competent, i.e., that p exceeds ½ (e.g., that each has an information sample of at least one bit) and that they choose independently of one another (e.g., their 1-bit samples are independently selected): (1) the proportion of the group that can be expected to choose correctly is p; (2) the probability P that the group, deciding on the basis of majority rule, makes the correct decision (i.e., the group's "collective competence") is greater than p, the level of individual competence; and furthermore (3) P increases as the size of the group increases and quite rapidly approaches perfection.

        2. The "Shades of Gray" Model. In an embellished and more interesting version of the theorem, each voter i has a distinct level of competence pi (perhaps reflecting a distinct levels of information), where each pi exceeds ½. The embellished Jury Theorem then states that: (1) the proportion of the group that can be expected to choose correctly is (the mean of the individual pi's); and (2) the group, deciding on the basis of majority rule, is more competent than the average member and, quite possibly, more competent than the most competent individual; and (3) collective competence P again increases with the size of the group (so that adding members to the group may increase group competence even as it reduces average individual competence) and quite rapidly approaches perfection.

        3. The "Black and White" Model. In this variant, a certain fraction F of the group is sufficiently informed to always choose correctly (p = 1), while the remaining fraction 1-F of the group is completely uniformed (p = ½). The proportion of the population expected to choose correctly is therefore F + ½(1-F) = ½(1+F), which exceeds ½ for any F > 0. It turns out that the collective competence P of a "black and white" group of a given size is no lower than that of a similarly sized "all gray" group with p = ½(1+F); in fact the collective competence of the "black and white" group is at least slightly higher.(1)

        4. The Multichotomous Model. Condorcet Jury Theorem variants have most commonly been applied to dichotomous choice situations (like true/false tests). But the basic setup can pretty readily be extended to multichotomous choice situations (like multiple-choice tests), most obviously the "black and white" variant. In a dichotomous choice situation, the (1-F) fraction of voters can be expected to split their choices equally between the two choices, one "correct" and the other "incorrect." In a multichotomous choice situation, the (1-F) fraction of voters can be expected to distribute their choices uniformly over all m options, one "correct" and m-1 "incorrect." Each incorrect option gets about (1-F)/m choices, while the correct option gets about F + (1-F)/m choices. In the probabilistic version, an individual has a probability p > 1/m of choosing the correct option and is equally likely to choose any incorrect option. In any event, if Condorcet-like assumptions hold, we would expect to see a more or less uniform distribution over the multiple options but with an additional frequency mass (whose magnitude depends on p, , or F) plumped on the correct answer. Regular or substantial deviations from this pattern of choices would indicate that Condorcet-like conditions do not hold.

        5. Statistical Interdependence. Standard Condorcet Jury Theorem variants assume that individual choices are statistically independent. In effect, it assumed that group members do not deliberate together or otherwise influence one another. In many contexts (indeed, in the jury context), this is not reasonable. Deliberation and mutual influence can be thought of as having two effects: first, they increase average individual competence ; second, they reduce the "effective number" of group members. The first effect increases collective competence, while the second reduces it, so the net effect is difficult to predict. While the problem presents difficult modelling problems, significant progress has been made (see Shapley and Grofman, 1983; Ladha, 1992, 1993; and Berg, 1993). In the empirical circumstances considered in the present paper, however, statistical independence seems reasonable.

        6. Subminimal Individual Competence. All the optimistic implications of Condorcet Jury Theorem variants are critically dependent on the assumption that each individual pi exceeds ½ (in a dichotomous choice situation) or 1/m (in a multichotomous situation), which is considered minimal competence. But if individual competence somehow falls below this level, the Condorcet Jury Theorem gets stood on its head: collective competence falls below average individual competence and approaches zero as group size increases. The assumption at least minimal competence in effect requires that there are no systematically misleading cues in the environment that will make individuals consistently more likely to choose incorrectly than correctly and, in a multichotomous choice situation, more likely to choose one incorrect option more than another.

        7. The Political or Conflicting Interests Model. It may be objected (see Black, 1958, p. 163) that all Condorcet Jury Theorem variants are irrelevant to the case of voting in a political context, because political choice involves the aggregation or reconciliation of conflicting preference, judgments, or interests, with the result that neither individual choices nor collective outcomes can be characterized as "correct" or "incorrect."

        But in fact a straightforward generalization of the Jury Theorem can be applied to political choices in which individual interests conflict (Miller, 1986a). In essence, we need only to admit that a choice that is "correct" for one individual may be "incorrect" for another. The Jury Theorem then can be generalized in the following fashion. In any dichotomous political choice situation, such as a referendum or two-party or two-candidate election, voters can be divided into two groups: those whose "true" interests lie in one direction and those whose "true" interests lie in the other direction. Let M > ½ be the fraction of voters in the larger of the two sets and we call the candidate, party, platform, etc., that serves their "true" interests the majority position.

        In this context, a voter's "true" interest (or "correct judgment") is to be thought of as the preference that he would have in the event that he were completely informed. And the competence of an individual voter is now the probability that he votes for the position, party, or candidate that best serves his true interest (and for which he would certainly vote in the event he were completely informed). Because of the arguments concerning rational ignorance (and for all the reasons identified in the empirical literature on public opinion and voting behavior), this probability likely falls far below certainty. Finally, we may say that the electoral outcome is "correct" when the interests of the majority prevail -- put otherwise, when the victorious position, party, or candidate is the one that would win in the event that all voters were completely informed. i.e., the majority position.

        The Jury Theorem can now be straightforwardly generalized to say that, if all voters are equally competent, whatever that level of competence (greater than ½), or more generally if the two groups of voters (divided in terms of their true interests) have the same average competence, then majority interests will probably prevail, and -- once the electorate achieves some minimum size -- this probability is greater than the average competence of all voters, increases further as the size of the electorate further increases, and then (at a rate that increases with M) approaches perfection. Moreover, the same conclusion may be reached if the two groups are of unequal average competence, provided only that the size of the majority group exceeds the size of the minority group by a ratio greater than deviation of average minority competence from ½ to the deviation of average majority competence from ½.

        We should note that while the expected electoral decision with any uniform p between ½ and 1 is the same as the electoral decision with a uniform p = 1, there is an expected attenuation effect, in that expected support for the majority position will be less than its "deserved" margin of M (but greater than ½). Let M* be this expected support. Given a uniform p level of individual competence, the majority position loses (1-p)M of its "true" supporters due to individual errors, while it gains (1-p)(1-M) of the supporters of the minority position. But, since M > ½, the loss always outweighs the gain. Thus M* lies between M and ½. Where M* lies within this interval depends on how much p exceeds ½ -- specifically, (M*-½)/(M-½) = 2(p-½). Thus relative attenuation, i.e., (M*-½)/(M-½), depends only on p; but absolute attenuation, i.e., M* - M, depends on M as well, increasing as M does. Note that the same attenuation effect occurs in the original Condorcet Jury Theorem, where M = 1 and M* = p.

        Thus, what the argument going back to Downs concerning the acquisition of political information has generally overlooked is that the apparent bad consequences for democracy and the electoral process resulting from rational ignorance are at least mitigated and perhaps reversed by the "statistical" mechanism identified by the Condorcet Jury Theorem and its extensions. Moreover, the same factor -- the large size of electorates that discourages voters from investing in political information -- also reduces the need for individual voters to be weil informed. Of course, this optimistic conclusion cannot be sustained if there are substantial inequalities (of a particular sort) in the distribution of political information. But it is worth re-emphasizing that it is fundamentally inequalities or biases in the distribution of information, and not generally low levels of information, that may undermine the collective performance of an electorate.

        These relatively optimistic theoretical conclusions rest, of course, on a number of assumptions, and it is not clear to what extent these assumptions are at least approximately realized in what actual circumstances. In the remaining sections of this essay, we look for empirical evidence of Condorcet-like effects.
 

3. Plurality Rule in Multiple-Choice Tests

        I first examine data that I had very readily at hand. Over the past twenty years or so, I have administered 127 multiple-choice tests in undergraduate classes.

        Each student on each test received a score equal to the number of questions answered correctly, divided by the total number of questions, and for each test there is a mean individual score. Over all tests, such mean individual performance is generally in the range of about .59-.65; the mean of such means is .617 (SD = .059). For each test, there is also a best individual score; over all tests, the mean best individual performance is .921 (SD = .058).

        I reviewed each test and, in effect, did the following. I generated one additional multiple-choice answer sheet for a fictitious test-taker C, representing the collective group of students taking each test. C's answer to each question was determined by the modal or plurality answer given by all students who took the test. C's answer sheet was then checked against the answer key and received a score representing collective performance in the same manner as each student, except that when two answers, one of which was correct, were tied in the modal position C got half credit.

        It is clear that Condorcet-like conditions did not always underlie student choice behavior. There was no consistent tendency for responses to be even approximately uniformly distributed over wrong options. Clearly some questions were "tricky" and included an appealing but incorrect option, which attracted a very disproportionate share of responses. Moreover, questions were often repeated in identical or only slightly modified form from semester to semester, and the same distinctive clustering of responses appeared each time. Thus the assumption of better than minimal individual competence certainly did not hold for very question.

        Nevertheless overall Condorcet-like effects are very evident and of considerable magnitude. In every one of the 127 tests, collective performance substantially exceeded mean individual performance. The mean collective score was .866, giving an average leverage effect (improvement of collective performance over average individual performance) of .249. On the other hand, mean collective performance fell somewhat short of the mean best individual performance of .921. Typically, the leverage effect jumped C from the middle of the class to the top ranks of the class but usually not to the very top. C ranked uniquely in first place 15% percent of the time, tied for first place an additional 13% of the time, and at least tied for second place 47% of the time. C's median ranking was third place, and C ranked seventh or lower less than 10% of the time. The mean of all standardized collective scores was +1.64; typically individual scores were approximately normally distributed, so typically C stood at about the 95th percentile overall.
 

4. Political Information in the Electorate

        We now turn to examine political and electoral data more directly relevant to the motivating concerns of this paper. In the two remaining sections, we examine American National Election Study survey data from 1984 and 1988.(2) In this section, we in effect create dichotomous-choice tests for representative samples of the electorate concerning the positions of Presidential candidates on a variety of political issues, and we examine these test results somewhat as we examined the student test data in the previous section.

        We focus on questions of perceptual judgment that can, with reasonable objectivity, be scored as "correct" or "incorrect." These questions deal in particular with the (relative) positions of candidates on issues or on the ideological spectrum. For example, in 1984 NES respondents were asked:

        We hear a lot of talk these days about liberals and conservatives. Here is a seven-point scale on which the political views that people might hold are arranged from extremely liberal to extremely conservative.

        Where would you place yourself on this scale, or haven't you thought much about this?

[Asked only of people who are willing to place themselves on the scale, at least in response to a follow-up probe] Where would you place Ronald Reagan on this scale? Walter Mondale? The Democratic Party? The Republican Party?
Here is the distribution of responses to the latter set of questions:

                                                 Reagan          Mondale         Democrats      Republicans

        Liberal                                 10.2%             27.5%             29.6%               8.2%
        Slightly Liberal                       7.6%             18.0%             18.4%               7.8%
        Moderate                              8.8%             17.9%             14.8%             10.6%
        Slightly Conserv.                 12.2%                8.9%               8.3%             17.2%
        Conservative                       44.9%                9.9%             10.0%             37.5%
        DK/NA                             16.3%               17.9%            18.8%             18.6%
                                                100.0%             100.0%           100.0%           100.0%

        While these distributions suggest a fair amount of ideological confusion, respondents appear to be preponderantly correct in their judgments. We need to refine this assessment, however. For example, a respondent who was himself a really extreme conservative might put Reagan in the center or even on the liberal side of the scale and would thus appear in the frequency distribution above to be making an inaccurate judgment. However, such a respondent would at the same time probably view Mondale as being even further on the liberal side, so that his relative judgment would be quite accurate. Thus what we will do is combine each respondent's judgments on the placement of the pairs of candidates into a single measure indicating which candidate is judged to be more liberal (in this case), or which candidate is judged to be closer to a given issue position (in other cases). For the liberal/conservative candidate question in 1984, we get the following results:

        More Liberal Cand?                              %                  n                          Adj%                         %

        Correct             Mondale         1107         55.7%         1107         55.7%         77.8%         1390         69.9%

                                  Reagan             316         15.9%          316          15.9%        22.2%           599         30.1%
        In error             No Dif.            182           9.2%         1423                           100.0%
                                  DK/NA           384          19.3%          566         28.5%
                                                        1989         100.0%       1989        100.0%                           1989       100.0%

        The first pair of columns shows the overall distribution of respondents. Of all 1989 respondents, 1107 (55.7%) are scored, by their response to the two separate questions on each candidate, as "correct" by giving responses that imply that Mondale is more liberal, and the remaining respondents are in one way or other in error. Of the latter, 316 (15.9%) are flatly "incorrect," giving responses that imply that Reagan is more liberal, 182 (9.2%) are less flatly wrong, giving responses that imply that Reagan and Mondale occupy the same ideological position, and 384 (19.3%) are simply unable or unwilling to answer one or both questions or, more likely, the preceding question on their own ideological position (e.g., they "haven't thought much about it").

        We can rearrange this distribution in various ways to highlight different interpretations that can be linked up with our earlier theoretical discussion. The second pair of columns combines erroneous respondents in the No Difference (ND) and DK/NA categories. For some purposes, it is useful to put these respondents to one side and look at only at the others, who express definite "correct" or "incorrect" judgments. We can use the difference in frequency between "correct" and "incorrect" responses as a measure of how well informed a group is. In terms of the "black and white" model, this difference provides an estimate of the fraction F of the group that is informed. That is, in this case we might suppose that 28.5% of the respondents were uninformed and either admitted as much (DK/NA) or gave an evasive answer (ND), 15.9% were likewise uninformed but chose to guess and happened to guess wrong. But, since uninformed people in a dichotomous-choice situation are about equally likely to guess one way as another, we would estimate that another 15.9% or so of the respondents were also uninformed but chose to guess and happened to guess right. Thus applying the "black and white" model in this case, it appears that (1-F) = 28.5% + 15.9% + 15.9% = 60.2% and F = 55.7% - 15.9% = 39.8%.

        In sum, 28.5% + 15.9% = 44.3% of the individual respondents are in error on this judgment and 60.2% (including the lucky guessers) may be uninformed. At the same, the electorate collectively reaches the correct judgment based on majority rule. In the dichotomous choice situation, we know how 1423 will choose. We can make either of two assumptions concerning the remaining 566 respondents. We can suppose they will abstain from choosing, so that non-abstaining respondents choose Mondale over Reagan as more liberal by a margin of 77.8% to 22.2% (third set of percentages displayed); or we can suppose that the 566, when it is demanded that they actually make a choice, will guess randomly (as we infer about 15.9% + 15.9% = 28.8% of the respondents already have) and thus divide their choices about equally between the "correct" and "incorrect" answers and so choose Mondale or Reagan as more liberal by about the final set of percentages displayed.

        I repeated this kind of analysis for the "More Liberal Party" judgment, as well as judgments concerning candidate positions on the following political issues, in both the 1984 and 1988 election studies ("correct" answers are parenthetically shown):

Minority Aid: scale running from "the government and Washington should make every effort to improve the social and economic positions of blacks and other minorities" [Mondale/Dukakis] to "the government should not make any special effort to help minorities because they should help themselves [Reagan/Bush].
Government Services: scale running from "having the government provide fewer services to reduce spending" [Reagan/Bush] to "having the government provide more services even if it means increased spending" [Mondale/ Dukakis].
Job Guarantee: scale running from "having the government see that every person has a job and a good standard of living" [Reagan/Bush] to "letting each person get ahead on his own" [Mondale/Dukakis].
Defense Spending: scale running from "we should spend much less money on defense" [Mondale/Dukakis] to "defense spending should be greatly increased" [Reagan/Bush].
Central American Involvement (1984 only): scale running from "the U.S should be much more involved in the internal affairs of Central American countries" [Reagan] to "the U.S. should be much less involved in this area" [Mondale].
Health Insurance (1988 only): scale running from "government insurance plan that would cover all medical and hospital costs for everyone" [Dukakis] to "medical expenses should be paid by individuals are through private insurance plans like Blue Cross and other company paid plans" [Bush].
Cooperation with USSR: scale running from "we should try to cooperate more with Russia" [Mondale/Dukakis] to "we should be much tougher in our dealings with Russia" [Reagan/Bush].(3)
We do not repeat the tabular display and detailed analysis for each of the other 15 items, but summary data is provided below. For each year and issue, an information profile is shown corresponding the to the middle column (55.7%/15.9%/28.5%) in the "More Liberal Candidate" table above. The summary F measure is calculated for each item and averages are shown for each year.

                                   L/C          L/C         Min.     Govt.       Job          Def.        Am.         Coop.
            1984            Cand.       Party      Aid        Serv.     Guar.       Spend     Inv.         USSR

        Correct           55.7%     55.5%     51.5%     59.1%     52.3%     63.5%     44.0%     51.5%
        Incorrect         15.9%     15.8%      8.6%        9.3%       6.9%       5.8%      9.3%        8.6%
        ND/DK/NA      28.5%     28.7%     39.8%     31.6%     40.8%     30.6%     46.7%     39.8%

        F                       39.8%     39.7%     42.9%     49.8%     45.4%     57.7%     34.7%      42.9%
 

                                    L/C        L/C         Min.        Govt.     Job          Def.       Govt.       Coop.
            1988             Cand.     Party     Aid          Serv.    Guar.       Spend     Hlth.       USSR

        Correct            55.4%     54.0%     43.5%    46.9%     49.7%     57.7%     43.9%     29.7%
        Incorrect           11.8%     13.6%      6.8%     10.6%       9.2%       5.9%       6.9%     13.7%
        ND/DK/NA        32.8%     32.4%     49.6%    42.4%     41.2%     36.3%     49.2%     56.7%

        F                        43.3%     40.4%     36.7%    36.3%     40.5%     52.0%     37.0%     16.0%

        Combining all 16 items for the two election years, the average of information profile is 50.9%/9.9%/39.2%, for an overall F measure of 41.0%.(4) Thus typically about half of the electorate was making individual errors are barely 40% appeared to have the relevant information. Yet the electorate invariably rendered the correct collective judgment.

        How many individuals performed as well as the collectivity? Of course, the sample of respondents was different in the two years, so we have in effect two eight-item tests, one for each year. Here is the distribution of individual scores for each year:

            Score           1984                                                                       1988

                8         309         15.5%    <= Col. Score                        205          11.5%  <= Col. Score
                7         252         12.7%                                                  196          11.0%
                6         215         10.8%                                                  172            9.7%
                5         230         11.6%                                                  176            9.9%
                4         191           9.6%     <= mean ind (4.3)                  185          10.4%  <= mean ind (3.8)
                3         195           9.8%                                                  178          10.0%
                2         183           9.2%                                                  194          10.9%
                1         160           8.0%                                                  179          10.1%
                0         254          12.8%                                                 290          16.3%
                         1989        100.0%                                               1775         100.0%
 

5. Issue Referenda and Electoral Error

        In the preceding section, we examined information levels in the electorate in a manner parallel to the earlier analysis of errors in student multiple-choice tests. Accordingly our analysis entailed no "politics" -- no preferences, no conflicts, no votes, no outcomes. In this final section, we extend the analysis to bring in a kind of (simulated) politics, so that the analytical setup parallels the "conflicting interests" extension of the Condorcet Jury Theorem model discussed in section 2 and presented in detail in Miller (1986).

        In Section 4 we examined NES respondents' judgments concerning various issue positions of Presidential candidates. Before being asked such questions, each respondent was asked to indicate his or her own position on the issue in question (as the portion of the 1984 interview schedule on liberal vs. conservatives quoted near the beginning of Section 4 illustrates). Consider for example the 1984 question on defense spending:

"Some people believe that we should spend much less money for defense. Others believe that defense spending should be greatly increased. Where would you place yourself on this scale, or haven't you thought much about it?"
                   Greatly decrease                                     1             340             17.1%
                                                                                                                                    }        569         48.5%
                                                                                   2              229             11.5%

                                                                                   3              560             28.2%
                                                                                                                                    }        605         51.5%
                                                                                   4              318             16.0%

                  Greatly increase                                      5               287             14.4%

                  Haven't thought/DK/NA                                           255              12.8%

                                                                                                 1989            100.0%          1174        100.0%

        Let us suppose that a referendum were held on the question of whether defense spending should be increased or decreased. This partitions the electorate into three blocs: those who favor an decrease, those who favor an increase, and those who apparently are indifferent (occupying the middle position on the scale) or who have no opinion on the issue. Let us suppose that only those with clear preferences, i.e., those in the first two blocs, participate in the referendum. Then we see that the increase position wins, though only narrowly, by a 51.5% to 48.5% margin. We take this referendum outcome as the baseline for our analysis, in effect assuming that it represents the distribution of "true preferences" (in the sense of the discussion in Section 2) in the electorate. Accordingly, we take increase to be the majority position on the defense spending issue, and we take 51.5% to be its "deserved" level of support. Of course, the referendum does not really manifest "true" preferences, because these voters are (very) incompletely informed and, if they had more complete information, some would hold and express different opinions on the issue and would vote differently in the referendum. But a survey such as NES does not allow us empirically to assess this aspect of incomplete information. What it does allow us to do, however, is to look at incomplete information further down the political road and see how it changes individual choices and the collective outcome against the baseline of this referendum outcome.

        Suppose now that the 1174 voters who would participate in this referendum instead had the opportunity only to express their preferences indirectly by voting for candidates in an election, where the candidates have distinct positions on the issue in question, so voters can vote for candidates on the basis of their positions on the issue. Of course, voters characteristically are incompletely informed about candidate positions on any issue, so moving from the referendum to the election will introduce a fair amount of individual error. Our task is to assess the extent of this error and its impact on the electoral outcome and electoral decision.(5)

        Though many individual voters make errors of judgment, the Condorcet Jury Theorem style of argument suggests that the referendum and electoral outcomes are likely to be quite similar and, in particular, that the two processes will typically yield the same majority-rule decision (though we may have doubts on this particular issue, because the referendum outcome is so close). We also have the further theoretical expectation that the election will reflect the attenuation effect, the relative magnitude of which will depend on the extent of individual errors, but the direction of which is consistently to drive to the election closer to a 50%-50% split.

        As can be checked in Section 4, voters were actually exceptionally well informed on the defense spending issue in 1984: 63.5% reported the correct judgment, 5.8% the incorrect judgement, and the remaining 30.6% reported no judgment, giving an F of 52.0% -- the highest on any issue in either year. Moreover, this information profile belongs to the entire sample of 1989 respondents, and our present concern is only with the better informed (we would guess) subsample of 1174 respondents with clear preferences on the defense spending issue. If we restrict the information profile to the 1174 with clear preferences on the issue, 75.1% report the correct judgment, 6.6% the incorrect judgement, and the remaining 18.3% no judgment, giving an F of 68.5%. Still, in an absolute sense, many individual voters have erroneous judgments.

        Next we must decide what respondents in the ND/DK/NA category with respect to candidate judgments will do in the election. There are two possibilities: such voters may abstain, reducing turnout but increasing F); or such voters may vote randomly and so can be expected to split their votes equally between the two candidates. The resulting error rates for the Defense Spending issue in 1984 are summarized below:

                                    All voters partici-             All voters participating in election
                                pating in referendum     With Abstention        Without Abstention

        Correct             882         75.1%             882         92.0%             989.5         84.3%
        ND/DK/NA      215         18.3%
        Incorrect             77           6.6%                77           8.0%              84.5         15.7%
                               1174        100.0%            959         100.0%          1174         100.0%

        Let us consider how the referendum outcome is affected by individual errors as it is transformed into an electoral outcome. Three factors produce electoral error, i.e., the discrepancy between the referendum and electoral outcomes. The first (given an election with abstention) is the abstention effect which from the fact that in general abstainers will not be distributed between supports of the majority and minority positions in exactly the same way as all referendum participants. The second is the attenuation effect has been previously discussed. Calculation of the attenuation effect uses the appropriate overall error rate such as shoWn above for Defense Spending, and it therefore presumes that errors rates are the same for supporters of the majority and minority positions. The third factor takes account of the information bias in error rates that arises when one group of supporters is better informed that the other.

        Let us now trace out these effects with respect to Defense Spending in 1984. This can be done by means of a simple cross-tabulation as shown in Table 1. The column variable is "true" voter preference on the issue, as indicated by the voter's referendum choice, and the column totals give the referendum outcome (51.5% for the majority position on this issue). The row variable is voter judgments concerning candidate positions on the issue, scored not by which candidate is judged closer to a given position but which candidate is judged closer to the voter's preferred position. Thus the column percentages in this crosstabulation show the information profiles among supporters of the majority and minority positions, respectively, but the positions of the "correct" and "incorrect" groups are interchanged in the two columns. The column totals with the middle row subtracted out give the number of "true" supporters of the majority and minority positions in an election with abstention (51.3% for the majority position). The totals of the top and bottom rows show the outcome of the election with abstention (50.8% for the majority position) and, when the center row total is equally allocated between them, the outcome of the election without abstention (50.6% for the majority position).

        In the case of Defense Spending in 1984, total electoral error is therefore -0.7% with abstention and -0.9% without abstention. To see how this error is apportioned between attenuation and information bias, we can calculate the expected electoral error that would result from error rates among both groups of supporters equal to the overall error rate. For Defense Spending in 1984, with abstention there are 492 supporters of the majority position and 467 of the minority position. Applying the overall error rate with abstention, the expected number of voters for the majority position in the election is 492 × .920 + 467 × .080 = 490 out of 959 nonabstaining voters or 51.1% -- an attenuation of 0.2% relative to the number of "true" supporters of the majority position in the non-abstaining electorate. (The attenuation effect is very slight because the error rate is quite low and because M barely exceeds 50% in the first place.) Thus the information bias is 50.8% - 51.1% = -0.3%, reflecting the fact that supporters of the minority position are slightly better informed than supporters of the majority position. Without abstention there are 605 supporters of the majority position and 569 of the minority position. Applying the overall error rate without abstention, the expected number of voters for the majority position in the election is 605 × .843 + 569 × .157 = 599.35 of 1174 referendum voters or 51.1% -- an attenuation of 0.4% relative to the number of "true" supporters of the majority position in the referendum electorate. These effects are summarized below the crosstabulation in Table 1.

        In this case, although (i) the referendum is very close, (ii) the majority position suffers a normal attenuation effect, and (iii) the minority has a very slight information advantage, the majority position still ekes out an extremely narrow electoral victory.(6)

        Table 2 shows similar summaries for all sixteen issues. Note that every table entry pertains to support for the majority position. (Thus the first entry on each line, i.e., the referendum outcome, is always greater than 50%.) We can see that the abstention effect typically hurts the majority position a bit -- that is supporters of the majority position on these issues typically are more likely to fall in the ND/DK/NA category than supporters of the minority position. The direction of the attenuation effect is necessarily toward a 50%-50% and thus always hurts the majority position unless electoral support for the majority position has already fallen below 50% due to abstention, as in the case of Government Services in 1984. The direction of information bias tends also to favor the minority position -- not as consistently as the abstention effect but with somewhat greater magnitude on average.

        The sample of sixteen issues produces a total of four collective errors, in which the election reverses the referendum outcome, for a collective performance of .75.(7) The reversals occur because of an information bias in favor of the minority position of sufficient magnitude.(8)

        Can we reach any general conclusions about collective performance in the face of conflicting interests in an electoral setting?

        First, it is worth reiterating that, on average, individual voters were frequently poorly informed and made many errors of judgment in all these simulated elections. On average, barely 60% of individual voters made correct judgments on a given issue (and, as we saw at the end of the last section, many fewer made consistently correct judgments). The average F score of about 45% indicates, in terms of the "black and white model," that less than one half of the voters on average actually had the requisite information reliably to vote correctly in an election.

        Collective performance was noticeably, but not dramatically, better than individual performance. This modest leverage effect essentially reflects the theoretical fact that collective competence is lower, other things being equal, in the face of conflicting interests than in the face of common interests. The reason for this, and the obvious reason for the four collective errors here, is that the margin of support for the majority position may barely exceed 50%. If so, "true" preferences (such as are taken to be expressed in the referenda) are rather likely to be reversed, even if electoral error is quite small (as it usually is). We should note that every collective error involved an issue in which the majority position received less than 55% support in the referendum. (There were seven such issues, and four of them produced collective errors.) On the other hand, none of the nine issues in which the majority position received more than 55% support in the referendum produced a collective error.

        While the collective error rate was 25%, average electoral error was only 5.5%. (This is the average absolute error, ignoring the direction of the error.) It is worth noting that average electoral error on the issues that produced collective errors was actually less (4.6%) than on the issues that did not produce collective errors (5.8%). However, this comes about because the issues that do not produce collective errors include all issues in which the majority position is strongly supported, and these issues necessarily have large (absolute) attenuation effects, which in turn tend produce large electoral errors. Restricting our attention to the seven issues in which the majority position received less than 55% support, electoral error averaged 4.6% among the four that produced collective errors but only 1.2% among the three that did not. The empirical conclusion is that marginal support for the majority position is necessary to produce collective error, which then will actually occur if there is significant electoral error produced by an information advantage in favor of the minority.
 


TABLES

Table 1 -- 1984 Defense Spending

                                                                             Referendum

Election
Increase Decrease
Candidate
451
(74.5%)
36
(6.3%)
487
(50.8%)
 
594.5
(50.6)
Thought 
ND/DK/NA
113
(18.7%)
102
(17.9%)
 
215
Closer to R's Mondale
(Decrease)
41
(6.8%)
431
(75.7%)
472
(49.2%)
 
579.5
(49.4%)
Position Nonabstaining
492
(51.3%)
467
(48.7%)
 

                                    Referendum        Abstention          Attenuation         Information             Electoral
                                       Outcome     +     Effect         +        Effect        +       Effect        =       Outcome

With abstention                51.5%                -0.2%                 -0.2%                 -0.3%                 50.8%
Without abstention           51.5%                   --                     -0.4%                 -0.5%                 50.6%
 
 

Table 2 --  Referendum Summaries

                                   Issue           Referendum    Abstention     Attenuation    Information          Electoral
         1984                                      Outcome   +    Effect     +      Effect     +    Bias      =           Outcome
 

Defense 51.5% -0.2% -0.2% -0.3% 50.8%
Spending 51.5% --- -0.4% 0.5% 50.6%
Job 57.9% +3.4% -2.4% +3.4% 62.3%
Guarantee 57.9% --- -3.5% +4.2% 58.6%
Minority 54.3% -2.5% -0.7% -3.4% **47.7%
Aid 54.3% --- -2.5% -3.4% **48.4%
Government 50.8% -2.0% +0.3% -1.5% **47.6%
Services 50.8% --- -0.3% -2.4% **48.1%
Cooperate. 54.0% -0.3% -1.1% -3.6% **49.0%
With USSR 54.0% --- -2.0% -2.7% **49.3%
Cent. Am. 68.4% -2.8% -5.4% -1.2% 59.0%
Involvement. 68.4% --- -10.0% -2.1% 56.3%
Lib/Con 61.8% +0.9% -4.2% +1.4% 59.9%
Candidate 61.8% --- -4.7% +1.8% 58.9%
Lib/Con 61.8% -0.4% -4.0% +1.3% 58.7%
Party 61.8% --- -4.8% +0.8% 57.8%

        1988

Defense 50.4% -0.3% 0.0% +2.9% 53.0%
Spending 50.4% --- 0.0% +1.8% 52.2%
Job 65.6% -1.1% -4.2% 0.0% 60.3%
Guarantee 65.5% --- -8.4% -0.5% 56.7%
Minority 64.8% -4.5% -3.0% -5.8% 51.5%
Aid 64.8% --- -8.6% -5.3% 50.9%
Government 53.9% -1.2% -1.0% -2.2% **49.5%
Services 53.9% --- -2.0% -2.3% **49.6%
Cooperate 58.2% -4.7% -2.2% -0.9% 50.4%
With USSR 58.2% --- -6.6% -1.4% 50.2%
Health 52.5% -1.7% -0.2% +1.7% 52.3%
Insurance 52.5% --- -1.4% +0.2% 51.3%
Lib/Con 66.7% -0.7% -4.4% -2.4% 59.2%
Candidate 66.7% --- -8.0% -1.7% 57.0%
Lib/Con 66.7% -0.9% -6.0% -2.0% 57.8%
Party 66.7% --- -9.7% -0.9% 56.1%

** Collective error (electoral decision is reverse of referendum decision)

Note: For each issue and year, the first line pertains to the election with abstention and the second to the election without abstention. All entries pertain to support for the majority position on the issue.
 
 

NOTES

An earlier version of this paper was presented at a conference on the Condorcet Jury Theorem organized by The Center in Political Economy, Washington University, St. Louis, Missouri, May 20-22, 1994. I thank Krishna Ladha for encouraging me to prepare a paper and Joe Oppenheimer for providing comments on it. I owe a very general debt to Bernard Grofman for bringing the Condorcet Jury Theorem to my attention almost twenty years ago. I owe a more specific debt to Kenneth Allen, who exactly twenty years ago showed me his revised graduate school paper on "Individual Errors and Aggregate Effects in Voting" -- a paper which regrettably has remained unpublished and from which the general analytic strategy in Section 5 is rather directly adapted. The data analyzed in Sections 4 and 5 were originally collected by the Center for Political Studies of the University of Michigan as part of the 1984 and 1988 American National Election Studies and were distributed by the Inter-University Consortium for Political Research. Parts of the exposition in Sections 1 and 2 are drawn from Miller (1986b).
 

1. This point is most obvious when F > ½, in which case collective competence of the "black and white" group is perfect whatever its size, whereas an "all gray" group with p = .75 is certainly less than perfectly competent, especially if the group is of small size.

2. For reasons of practical convenience, I have used the data sets distributed by the ICPSR to accompany the American Political Science Association's SETUPS teaching modules based on the 1984 and 1988 National Election Studies. Only respondents who were successfully interviewed both before and after the election are included, and certain variables have been combined or categories collapsed. In particular, the variables we use here were seven-point scales in the original data but in the present the two extreme pairs of points were collapsed, so five-point scales result.

3. Given the notable rapprochement between Reagan and Gorbachev that occurred between 1985 and 1988, one might question the "scoring" of this item in 1988, and indeed it is the outlier among the sixteen.

4. In an attempt to verify that the basic analysis was well-founded, I ran all respondents through a "Political Involvement Filter" measuring respondents' inclination and ability to acquire political information, and I separately analyzed those in the top and bottom categories. F figures for those in the bottom category typically approach zero percent; those for the top category average around 70-75%.

5. It may be worth noting explicitly that the outcome of this election depends solely on voters' preferences on the issue in question in conjunction with voters' judgments concerning candidate positions on the same issue. Voting choices in this (simulated) election are quite independent of voters preferences on other issues, perceptions of candidate stands on other issues, evaluations of candidates' personal qualities, party identification, voting habits, etc. In particular, this analysis make no use of voters' actual (reported) vote in the Presidential election.

6. And what is true about the electoral decision with abstention is also true without abstention, as must always be the case since the election outcome without abstention always lies between that of the election with abstention and a 50%-50% split.

7. Allen (1974), in his generally similar analysis of ten issues in 1964, found three collective errors, for a collective performance of .70.

8. The Minority Aid issue in both years illustrates the point that the information advantage is not always held by higher status, better educated, higher income, etc., groups, since on balance the well-informed minority on this issue scored lower than the less well informed majority on such demographic variables (income in particular). This issue in 1984 illustrates that, even if turnout is uniform, an intense and accordingly well-informed minority can win out over a more apathetic and accordingly less well informed majority by making fewer individual errors -- a theoretical point noted in Miller (1986a).
 
 

REFERENCES



Kenneth W. Allen (1974). "Individual Errors and Aggregate Effects in Voting." Unpublished Paper, University of Maryland Baltimore County.

Berelson, Bernard, Paul Lazarsfeld, and William McPhee (1954). Voting. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Berg, Sven (1993). "Condorcet's Jury Theorem, Dependency Among Jurors." Social Choice and Welfare, 10:87-95.

Berg, Sven (1994). "Majority Functions Based on Extensions of the Binomial Distribution." Paper presented at the Second International Conference of the Society for Social Choice and Welfare, Rochester, New York, July 8-11, 1994.

Black, Duncan (1958). The Theory of Committees and Elections. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Downs, Anthony (1957). An Economic Theory of Democracy. New York: Harper & Row.

Grofman, Bernard (1975). "A Comment on 'Democratic Organization: A Preliminary Mathematical Model'," Public Choice, 21:99-103.

Grofman, Bernard (1978). "Judgmental Competence of Individuals and Groups in a Dichotomous Choice Situation: Is a Majority of Heads Better Than One?" Journal of Mathematical Sociology, 6:497-60.

Grofman, Bernard, Guillermo Owen, and Scott Feld (1983). "Thirteen Theorems in Search of the Truth," Theory and Decision, 15:261-278.

Grofman, Bernard, and Scott Feld (1988). "Rousseau's General Will: A Condorcetian Perspective," American Political Science Review, 82:567-576.

Key, V. O., Jr. (1966). The Responsible Electorate. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

Ladha, Krishna K. (1992). "The Condorcet Jury Theorem, Free Speech and Correlated Voters," American Journal of Political Science, 36:617-634.

Ladha, Krishna K. (1993). "Condorcet's Jury Theorem in Light of De Finetti's Theorem," Social Choice and Welfare, 10:69-85.

McKelvey, Richard D., and Peter C. Ordeshook (1985). "Elections With Limited Information: A Fulfilled Expectations Model Using Contemporaneous Poll and Endorsement Data as Information Sources," Journal of Economic Theory, 36:55-85.

McKelvey, Richard D., and Peter C. Ordeshook (1986). "Information, Electoral Equilibrium, and the Democratic Ideal," Journal of Politics, 48:909-937.

McKelvey, Richard D., and Peter C. Ordeshook (1990). "Information and Elections: Retrospective Voting and Rational Expectations." In John A. Ferejohn and James H. Kuklinski, eds., Information and Democratic Processes. Urbana: University of Illinois Press.

Miller, Nicholas R. (1986a). "Information, Electorates, and Democracy: Some Extensions and Interpretations of the Condorcet Jury Theorem." In Bernard Grofman and Guillermo Owen, eds., Information Pooling and Group Decision Making. Greenwich: JAI Press.

Miller, Nicholas R. (1986b). "Public Choice and the Theory of Voting: A Survey." In Samuel Long, ed., Annual Review of Political Science, Vol. 1. Norwood, NJ: Ablex Publishing Corporation.

Owen, Guillermo, Bernard Grofman, and Scott L. Feld (1989). "Proving a Distribution-Free Generalization of the Condorcet Jury Theorem." Mathematical Social Sciences, 17:1-16.

Page, Benjamin I., and Robert Y. Shapiro. The Rational Public. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1992.

Schumpeter, Joseph A. Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy. New York: Harper & Row, 1942.

Shapley, Lloyd, and Bernard Grofman (1984). "Optimizing Group Judgmental Accuracy in the Presence of Interdependencies," Public Choice, 43:329-343.